The rule book

Published May 25, 2023
The writer is a lawyer based in Islamabad.
The writer is a lawyer based in Islamabad.

ONE way to view the Constitution and other laws, is to consider them as a rule book, something akin to the rules of playing a sport, or a game of chess. Because the level of complexity of governing a society is much greater and the number of stakeholders higher, the Constitution and the statutes often employ broader standards or principles, rather than just the bright-line rules.

Irrespective, there are bright-line rules in the Constitution. One such rule, for instance, states that upon the dissolution of a provincial assembly, elections are to be held no later than 90 days. If the people in a particular society are to be governed by the elected representatives that the people choose, then, there is only a period of 90 days and no more, during which an interim set-up can occupy the space, which rightfully only belongs to the elected representatives.

There are at least two potential issues when a society, a group of people, or a set of players, adopts a fixed code of rules or standards. First, there are problems that emanate from interpretation. Shakespeare articulated an observation — which we are all privy to thanks to our experiences — that even the devil can cite the scriptures for his purpose.

Hassan Niazi, in ‘Playing for Keeps: Pakistan’s Experience with Constitutional Hardball in 2022’ (Pakistan Law Review) has argued, in the context of the politico-constitutional crises of 2022, that self-serving interpretations, which remain possible and even plausible, but are, nonetheless, hardball interpretations, end up leading to a race to the bottom, with each round becoming more acrimonious than the last for the players involved. One’s political end-point can have a huge bearing on the interpretations one extends to the text that is being interpreted.

The morality of the law cannot be separated from the letter of the law.

Second, and the greater of the two issues, arises when those rules or standards, presumably agreed upon, or deemed to be agreed upon, are partially suspended under one pretext or another. Any game in which this happens would necessarily lead to the end of that game. For instance, if a knight on a chessboard begins to move freely, as if it were the queen, the game of chess, as we know it, would not remain that game but become something else.

If these rules give way or change not in accordance with how they are supposed to be changed (which the rules may themselves specify) but through some arbitrary fiat, just because the rules can be changed at any given point, then, at a minimum, the confidence in those rules will be undermined, even if the other players continue to play.

Both these issues often do not necessarily turn on the letter of the rules, or their substance. Underlying both these issues is something more fundamental: a lack of basic morality, or adherence to foundational principles. The morality of the law cannot be separated from the letter of the law.

The reason why the rules of chess, for instance, have endured since ages is primarily because the game makes the rules and their application reciprocal — in fact, symmetrical. There is an inbuilt fairness in the game, with a symmetrical board, an equal number of pieces, and the pieces performing the same functions for both players.

The written set of rules can be any rules, but undergirding them, there ought to be the foundational ‘Golden Rule’, which provides the moral underpinnings: do unto others as you would like done to you. Whatever the rules, when the application of these rules is brought to bear against a person, their family or their tribe, that person should not have a reason to decry them as unfair. White chessboard pie­ces or black, it does not matter. This is perhaps what John Rawl’s Veil of Ignorance is also geared towards.

To make the application of rules in a society fair, one provision or standard does much more work than others: the equal treatment or protection of law clause. If anyone is given any treatment deemed special, then everyone, similarly placed, is entitled to that special treatment. Sitting in power, with the largesse of the state at one’s disposal, if one bestows special treatment on oneself and one one’s accomplices, then everyone is entitled to the same treatment. Or no one is.

If the vision of the law is such that it is to be used as an instrument against one’s opponents, and as a facilitative mechanism for oneself and one’s friends, then finding fault with the law is not enough: what is to be mourned is the absence of morality.

And more than the law, we just need basic morality.

The writer is a lawyer based in Islamabad.

awahid@umich.edu

Published in Dawn, May 25th, 2023

Opinion

Editorial

Military convictions
Updated 22 Dec, 2024

Military convictions

Pakistan’s democracy, still finding its feet, cannot afford such compromises on core democratic values.
Need for talks
22 Dec, 2024

Need for talks

FOR a long time now, the country has been in the grip of relentless political uncertainty, featuring the...
Vulnerable vaccinators
22 Dec, 2024

Vulnerable vaccinators

THE campaign to eradicate polio from Pakistan cannot succeed unless the safety of vaccinators and security personnel...
Strange claim
Updated 21 Dec, 2024

Strange claim

In all likelihood, Pakistan and US will continue to be ‘frenemies'.
Media strangulation
Updated 21 Dec, 2024

Media strangulation

Administration must decide whether it wishes to be remembered as an enabler or an executioner of press freedom.
Israeli rampage
21 Dec, 2024

Israeli rampage

ALONG with the genocide in Gaza, Israel has embarked on a regional rampage, attacking Arab and Muslim states with...